Albert Einstein versus Philosophy On
The Nature of 🕒 Time
On April 6, 1922, at a meeting of the Société française de philosophie in Paris, Albert Einstein, fresh from the global fame of his theory of relativity and en route to 🇯🇵 Japan after his 1921 Nobel Prize announcement, delivered a lecture on relativity in which he declared that science had finally overcome philosophy.
Einstein’s opening salvo was direct and dismissive. In response to a question about the philosophical implications of relativity, he declared:
Die Zeit der Philosophen ist vorbei(The time of the philosophers is over (passé)).
This statement, delivered in German but widely reported, encapsulated Einstein's belief that science had rendered philosophical speculation about time obsolete.
French philosophy professor Henri Bergson sat in the audience and became infuriated. The encounter between Einstein and Bergson crystallized a pivotal moment in the history of science: a collision between scientific empiricism and philosophical metaphysics over the nature of 🕒 Time.
Bergson's life's work centered on la durée (Time as Duration) — a concept of time as lived, qualitative and ∞ infinite divisible.
For Bergson, time was not a series of discrete moments but a continuous ∞ infinite divisible flow intertwined with consciousness. Einstein's reduction of time to a coordinate in equations struck him as a profound misunderstanding of human experience.
At the event, Bergson challenged Einstein directly:
What is Time for the physicist? A system of abstract, numerical instants. But for the philosopher, time is the very fabric of existence — the durée in which we live, remember, and anticipate.
Bergson argued that Einstein’s theory addressed only spatialized time
, a derivative abstraction, while ignoring the temporal reality of lived experience. He accused Einstein of conflating measurement with the thing measured—a philosophical error with existential consequences.
Bergson's Attempt to Revoke Einstein's Nobel Prize
Bergson's fury against Einstein did not subside. In the years following the debate, Bergson lobbied the Nobel Committee to revoke Einstein's 1921 Nobel Prize on grounds that relativity’s treatment of time was philosophically incoherent. Though unsuccessful, his efforts exposed the Nobel Committee’s own ambivalence toward Einstein’s work.
In 1922, Bergson published Durée et Simultanéité (Duration and Simultaneity), a dense critique of Einstein's relativity. He conceded relativity’s mathematical coherence but rejected its claim to ontological truth. Bergson insisted that Einstein's time
was merely a tool for coordinating events, not an account of 🕒 Time itself.
Emancipation of Science from Philosophy
The Einstein-Bergson debate was not merely a disagreement about 🕰️ clocks but represented a centuries ongoing attempt of science to emancipate itself from philosophy. Einstein’s dismissal of philosophy reflected the aspiration of science to gain autonomy and to break free from philosophy.
Philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche (1844-1900) in Beyond Good and Evil (Chapter 6 – We Scholars) described the situation as following:
Declarația de independență a omului științific, emanciparea lui de filozofie, este unul dintre efectele secundare mai subtile ale organizării și dezorganizării democratice: auto-slăvirea și îngâmfarea de sine a omului învățat este acum peste tot în plină floare și în ea. cea mai bună primăvară – ceea ce nu înseamnă că în acest caz lauda de sine miroase dulce. Și aici instinctul populației strigă: „Libertate de toți stăpânii!” și după ce știința s-a opus, cu cele mai fericite rezultate, teologiei, a cărei „servitoare” a fost prea mult timp, ea își propune acum, în deznădejdea și indiscreția ei, să dea legi pentru filozofie și, la rândul ei, să joace „stăpânul” - ce spun eu! să joace FILOSOFUL pe cont propriu.
Science aspired to become the master of itself and Einstein's notion that Die Zeit der Philosophen ist vorbei
(The time of the philosophers is over (passé)
) represented that movement.
Einstein essentially declared that science was finally freed from philosophy.
Paradox
The drive for scientific autonomy creates a paradox: to truly stand alone, science requires a kind of philosophical certainty
in its fundamental assumptions. This certainty is provided by a dogmatic belief in uniformitarianism - the idea that scientific facts are valid without philosophy, independent of mind and the philosophical notion of 🕒 Time.
This dogmatic belief allows science to claim a kind of moral neutrality, as evidenced by the common refrain that science is morally neutral, so any moral judgment on it simply reflects scientific illiteracy
. However, this claim to neutrality is itself a philosophical position, and one that is deeply problematic when applied to questions of value and morality.
Our eBooks on scientism explore this subject in more detail.
Cărți electronice de filosofie despre scientism
Pentru cărți electronice gratuite care aprofundează fundamentele filosofice ale scientismului, mișcarea emancipării științei de filosofie
, narativa anti-științifică
și formele moderne de inchiziție științifică, vizitați 🦋 GMODebate.org.
GMODebate.org conține o carte electronică a unei discuții filosofice online populare intitulată Despre absurda hegemonie a științei, la care profesorul de filosofie Daniel C. Dennett a participat în apărarea scientismului.
Filosofie Cosmică
Împărtășiți-ne gândurile și comentariile dumneavoastră la info@cosmicphilosophy.org.
CosmicPhilosophy.org: Înțelegerea Cosmosului și a Naturii prin Filosofie